

A surprising consequence of dynamical resonances is that an experienced player may benefit sometimes more from an unloaded than from a loaded barbell.

Our analysis reveals, for the simplest possible non-trivial dice throwing model, the effect of dice loading. We show how, depending on the initial conditions, dissipation during bounces, and mass asymmetry, the degree of unpredictability varies. Here, we complete the picture by considering the general asymmetric case of unequal masses. In order to keep things simple, we focused on the symmetrical case of equal masses. E 78 036207 featured in 2008 NatureĤ55 434), we proposed a simplified model to analyze the origin of the pseudorandomness: a barbell with two masses at its tips with only two final outcomes. However, throwing a fair cube is a dissipative process that is well described by deterministic classical mechanics. Fisher’s are conceptually different.ĭice tossing is commonly believed to be random. This point has ramifications for the question of how Darwin’s theory of evolution and R. Evolutionary theory is right to focus on traits, rather than on token individuals, because the fitnesses of token organisms (as opposed to their actual survivorship and degree of reproductive success) are almost always unknowable. A plausible philosophical thesis about supervenience entails that the twins are equally fit if they live in identical environments, but evolutionary biology is not committed to the thesis that the twins live in identical environments. This is because the theory of natural selection is fundamentally about the fitnesses of traits, not the fitnesses of token individuals. Here it is argued that evolutionary theory has no commitment, one way or the other, as to whether the twins are equally fit. Michael Scriven’s (1959) example of identical twins (who are said to be equal in fitness but unequal in their reproductive success) has been used by many philosophers of biology to discuss how fitness should be defined, how selection should be distinguished from drift, and how the environment in which a selection process occurs should be conceptualized. Clearly, the process underlying the generation of a random variable matters. Consequently, the condition of fairness leads to a different answer, as shown in figure 1b. For example, the possible orientations of a coin spun end over end about a diameter are limited to a circle, not a sphere. But von Neumann's mathematically plausible interpretation is impossible for a real tossed coin, which must conserve angular momentum and thus cannot explore all possible orientations. Then the question boils down to asking what the thick-ness of the coin should be so that the areas of its sides and the faces are equal when projected onto the circumscribing sphere that characterizes the possible orientations figure 1a shows the geometry. But how did he answer the question? Presumably, he assumed that all possible orientations of the coin are equally likely. To illustrate the principle in the context of a coin toss, we pose the following question: How thick should a coin be to have a 1/3 chance of landing on edge? John von Neumann is said to have solved the problem instantly on hearing of it, giving 0.354 for the aspect ratio (thickness divided by diameter)-a three-decimal approximation of 1/(2√2 ‾). The idea is that in a random process, probabilities are ill-defined unless one spec-ifies the nature of the process that leads to the random vari-able. Randomness defined The considerations noted above raise a fundamental issue in probability, termed Bertrand's paradox. And even if it flips, it might not do so fre-quently instead, it could wobble like a Frisbee and thus still be biased to land with its starting side up. For example, a coin that does not flip even once will end up the same way it started.


Another route is based on symmetry since a coin of zero thickness can land on either of two equivalent faces, the probabilities for each must be the same. An empirical approach based on repeated experiments might suggest that the result is approximately correct. However, that is not typically how one approaches the ques-tion. Why is the outcome of a coin toss random? That is, why is the probability of heads 1/2 for a fair coin? Since the coin toss is a physical phenomenon governed by Newtonian mechanics, the question requires one to link probability and physics via a mathematical and statistical description of the coin's motion.
